The following recently-published articles display some of our current misconceptions, fantasies,
and worries about the brain, mind, and self. Such essays by learned experts help define who we are, how we treat others, and what our future might be. They therefore merit our attention and their arguments should not be accepted based on an implied argument from authority. What are they trying to tell us about these important matters and why?
“Possessive Individualism: Can We Really Own Ourselves?” by John
Médaille, The Imaginative Conservative, December
2013
“Endless fun: The question is not whether we can upload our brains onto a computer, but what will become of us when we do”
by Michael Graziano, Aeon Magazine,
December
18, 2013
Notice that all three articles are not published in
professional, peer-reviewed scientific or philosophical journals, rather in
periodicals intended for widespread public consumption. What they write in science and philosophy
journals has less impact because the circle of readership is smaller. Therefore, all of us should be concerned
about the impact of their ideas on the global public through articles such as
those above. Why? Because how we as everyday people treat
ourselves and others is largely influenced by such public-targeted articles and
books. If our concepts of our selves and
the selves of others are given inaccurate meanings, touted as something that scientists want to prove are of lesser significance compared to the functioning of our genes and brains, or when our selves are wistfully
portrayed as virtual commodities that might one day live forever embedded in
computers, our lives and treatment of each other may easily become adversely
affected. The facts and argumentation in
all such for-public-consumption writings should be treated with skepticism and
subjected to scrutiny.
John Médaille, an adjunct instructor of theology at the University
of Dallas , claims that each of
us does not own that which we commonly call our “self” or “person.” He believes that our self is a gift from
other people. David Gelernter, a
professor of computer science at Yale, warns that science is trying to destroy
or make our selves irrelevant. Finally, Michael Graziano, a professor of psychology and neuroscience at Princeton ,
asks us to imagine a disembodied self living forever in a computer with freedom
to experience anything we can imagine.
When such treatments of this topic present us with distortions
and foreboding we should not be surprised that many people find it disturbing. After all, we are talking about something –
our self, our person – that is very intimate and private. Many people, especially those of a
secular-scientific bent, think of their self as their very special, unique once-for-all-eternity
existence. Conversely, nearly two-thirds
of the world’s people believe in a deity and some kind of life for their
respective selves after their bodily death.
To them their mind, self, person, and soul are one. Such believers go to considerable extremes to
live in a manner that, they have been told, will provide a comfortable and
peaceful afterlife for all eternity for their self after their body ceases to
live.
When someone mucks around with core definitions of what we
think we know about the personal, private existence of our self and its future,
we pay attention, close attention. It is
understandably worrisome to most of us when we learn of unusual or disturbing
claims about the self. We are shaken
when we read worrisome essays about the possible end or eventual
meaninglessness of the self, our self – that which, and who, we think we
are. The self that, during each conscious
moment we are alive, retains ideas about who we are, the things we do, and why
we do them. This self is as good as we
get and most of us wish to keep it intact, meaningful, and alive. What are some of these disturbing assertions? Do they have any merit in light of what we
know about the mind and body from the evidence of biological and psychological
science?
Possessive Individualism
Ownership is generally defined as being in possession of or having
something. In its formal sense,
ownership means having legal title or right to something - mere possession is
not ownership.
John Médaille’s discussion of the self is couched in terms
of its ownership and its importance in social exchanges. Neither approach, ownership or exchange, tells
us what a self is, how it originates, and how it operates within the natural
and social worlds it inhabits.
I disagree with Médaille’s view that “of all the objects in
the universe, the one thing we cannot own is ourselves” because, he says, “we
cannot create ourselves.” To originate
or produce something is not a necessary or sufficient condition for owning it. The slaves who constructed the Great Pyramid of Giza in 2560BC accrued no ownership of that structure, legal or otherwise. Further, to have something in one’s possession
- a rental car - or as an integral part of one’s corporal being – an artificial
heart implanted but not yet paid for – is not a necessary and sufficient
condition for one having exclusive ownership of it. Also, Médaille’s comparison of the potential
ownership of the self to ownership of real property and wealth is not
helpful.
Médaille further states that each of us is “called into being through an act of love into the ready-made community of the family.” This is misleading in that it imputes an anthropomorphic, unilineal cause-and-consequence process to life – a community wills a self into existence. The bio-behavioral reality of all life on Earth is characterized by many components and processes that are causally complex, contextual, and mutually interdependent.
Médaille further states that each of us is “called into being through an act of love into the ready-made community of the family.” This is misleading in that it imputes an anthropomorphic, unilineal cause-and-consequence process to life – a community wills a self into existence. The bio-behavioral reality of all life on Earth is characterized by many components and processes that are causally complex, contextual, and mutually interdependent.
Médaille calls the social and cultural components communities
provide the individual, “gifts.” I think
this is misleading in that it anthropomorphs community and society as
conscious agents that willfully provide for individuals. In reality, that which the community provides
are no more “gifts” than the sunlight, air, land, and water are gifts to
Earth’s living plants and animals. These
natural entities exist and provide conditions favorable to sustaining
life. Such resources are not parceled
out as gifts by the planet any more than human communities give selves as gifts. Community norms and support exist, and human
beings who are born into communities make use of them.
We cannot say that we do not own our selves because we cannot “seize control of our origins or be present at our beginnings.” We cannot claim that we do not own our selves because they are dependent upon the nurturing and moral gifts of communities. I have argued elsewhere that there is a reciprocal relationship between the self and the community where, if we use Médaille’s notion, the individual and his/her self is as much a “gift” to the community as is the nurturing and knowledge provided by the group a gift to the individual.
We cannot say that we do not own our selves because we cannot “seize control of our origins or be present at our beginnings.” We cannot claim that we do not own our selves because they are dependent upon the nurturing and moral gifts of communities. I have argued elsewhere that there is a reciprocal relationship between the self and the community where, if we use Médaille’s notion, the individual and his/her self is as much a “gift” to the community as is the nurturing and knowledge provided by the group a gift to the individual.
Médaille’s description of Liberalism seems over-simplified. Liberalism is far more responsive to its
origins in the group and its dependency upon the group’s affirmation than Médaille
concedes. Liberalism, he claims,
portrays the group as a threat to the emergence and freedom of the self. To “find ourselves,” he says, proponents of
Liberalism believe “we must lose the community, or at least lose any
restrictions the community would impose, other than those we voluntarily
select.” There is a dynamic between the
demands of the group and the freedom of individuals but this is not a zero-sum,
all-or-nothing process. The
individualism of Liberalism can and must be expressed within the constraining
contexts provided by the community. A
Liberalism that only complies with the societal constraints it voluntarily
selects runs the risk of damaging or destroying the conservative, stabilizing
aspects of community life. This, in
turn, will likely lead to anarchy and the failure of society. Surely Médaille has mis-characterized
Liberalism or set it up as a straw man.
The Scientific Attack on the Self
Computer simulation of the branching
architecture of the dendrites of pyramidal neurons. Wikipedia.
Computer scientist David Gelernter provides an accurate
treatment of the self in the context of the mind-body problem. Contrary to what you might expect given his
training and expertise in computer science, Gelernter objects strongly to the
comparison of the mind and brain to the software and hardware of a computer. His five flaws of computationalism (AKA,
cognitivism) are noteworthy:
1. You can
transfer a program easily from one computer to another, but you can’t transfer
a mind, ever, from one brain to another.
2. You can run
an endless series of different programs on any one computer, but
only one “program” runs, or ever can run, on any one human brain.
3. Software is
transparent. I can read off the precise state of the entire program at any
time. Minds are opaque—there is no way I can know what you are thinking unless
you tell me.
4. Computers
can be erased; minds cannot.
5. Computers
can be made to operate precisely as we choose; minds cannot.
Gelernter’s insights, regrettably, are overshadowed by his
hyperbolic, name-calling tirade against scientists and philosophers of mind he
argues are in the forefront of a deliberate all-out “assault on the phenomenon
known as subjectivity.” Their views, he says, “are threatening all sorts of
intellectual and spiritual fields.” This
“problem,” he claims, “originated at the intersection of artificial
intelligence and philosophy of mind – in the question of what consciousness and
mental states are all about…” He traces
the roots of the problem to early 20th Century behaviorism and
accuses binary electronic computing of lighting the “fuse of an intellectual
crisis that blasted off in the 1960s and has been gaining altitude ever
since.” [I suppose for good measure he
could have thrown in Edward O. Wilson (Sociobiology:The New Synthesis (1975)) as someone who also sought and encouraged the diminution
of the self/person.] Not surprisingly, Gelernter
agrees with Thomas Nagel (Mind and Cosmos,
(2012)) that “Darwinian evolution is insufficient to explain the emergence
of consciousness – the capacity to feel and experience the world.”
I do not share Gelernter’s foreboding worry that science is
trying to destroy subjectivity. Scientific inquiry into mind-brain matters
should be allowed to go apace constrained only by provisional, reasonable, and
ethical standards and laws. Scientific inquiry will not and cannot defeat much
less destroy our humanness, humaneness, or humanity. Consciousness and self are
the wellspring and driving forces of science without which the establishment
and growth of scientific knowledge would be impossible.
I likewise do not share Gelernter and Nagel’s view that
Darwinian evolution (understood as a pluralistic theoretical and methodological
approach, as it should be) cannot account for the emergence of
consciousness. I do, however, object to
a narrow, scientistic reductionism that reduces the understanding of the self,
person, and subjectivity solely to a mapping and accounting of the genetic
chemistry and neurophysiology of the brain, or relegates states of mind and
subjectivity to the out-box of irrelevant epiphenomena.
Returning to Gelernter, he begins his discussion of
consciousness by asking the wrong questions:
“So why should we humans be
equipped with consciousness? So why
would nature have taken the trouble to invent an elaborate thing like
consciousness, when it could have gotten off without it just as well?” The process of evolution by natural selection
does not invent and imbue characteristics upon species because they “should”
have them or need them. Novel anatomical
and physiological characteristics and behavior potentials arise via various
mechanisms inherent in living matter and the natural environment. Some prove adaptive and contribute to the
survival and reproduction of individuals.
Others do not. Gelernter trots
out philosopher David Chalmers to help argue that the emergence of
consciousness does not follow logically from what we know of our Universe. A Universe like ours sans consciousness, he
says, is entirely plausible. He’s
right. But questions of why nature
invented consciousness when the Universe could get along quite well without it
are irrelevant at best, inane and misleading at worst.
Consciousness, in human evolutionary history, was an
unanticipated emergent property that arose from the brain functions of higher
animals. How this occurred is, and
likely will remain, unknown. In the
human evolutionary lineage consciousness proved to be especially adaptive when brain
states began being expressed socially using symbolic language. That complex matters about the food and
dangers of the natural world and the emotional, political conditions of the
social world could then be couched in discussions that were not bound by time
or place was a quantum leap in our otherwise meager (relatively small teeth,
weak muscles) adaptive repertoire. I see
no reason why a Darwinian evolutionary explanation of consciousness and self based
on paleoarchaeology, psychology, genetics, and neuroscience cannot, someday, be
a compelling, provisional truth of science.
Gelernter has particular disdain for Ray Kurzweil (The Singularity is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology, (2005)) and
the technologist and inventor’s claim that by 2045 machine intelligence will
dominate human intelligence:
Whether
he knows it or not, Kurzweil believes in and longs for the death of
mankind. Because if things work out as
he predicts, there will still be life on Earth, but no human life. To predict that a man who lives forever and
is built mainly from semiconductors is still a man is like predicting that a
man with stainless steel skin, a small nuclear reactor for a stomach, and an IQ
of 10,000 would still be a man.”
Regarding the self, subjectivity, and mind Gelernter has
more useful and plausible ideas to offer:
Subjectivity
is your private experience of the world:
your sensations; your mental life and inner landscape; your experiences
of sweet and bitter, blue and gold, soft and hard; your beliefs, plans, pains,
hopes, fears, theories, imagined vacation trips and gardens and girlfriends and
Ferraris, your sense of right and wrong, good and evil. This is your subjective world. It is as real as the objective physical
world.
…
The mind
has its own structure and laws: It has
desires, emotions, imagination; it is conscious. But no mind can exist apart from the brain
that “embodies” it. Yet the brain’s
structure is different from the mind’s.
The brain is a dense tangle of neurons and other cells in which neurons
send electrical signals to other neurons downstream via a wash of
neurotransmitter chemicals….
The most important takeaways from Gelernter’s essay
are: Subjectivity matters in our
understandings of Humankind.
Subjectivity cannot be reduced to and explained solely by chemistry and
physics.
A Virtual-Reality Afterlife
Simplified diagram of Spaun, a 2.5-million-neuron
computational model of the brain. (A)The corresponding physical regions
and connections of the human brain. (B) The mental architecture of
Spaun. Wikipedia.
Finally, consider the essay by neuroscientist Michael
Graziano on the possibility of a virtual-reality afterlife. He violates all that Gelernter asserts
regarding the necessary embedment of consciousness and the self in the
biological body. Graziano lightly
addresses but essentially passes by the question of whether or not a version or
replica of a self can actually be the same
as a self; or how a self could continue to exist without a sentient biological human
body (and brain) that most agree is a necessary part of our self, person,
subjectivity, and mind states. Body and
mind are one. When the body dies, self
ceases to exist. These are the basic
tenets of monism, by far the dominant paradigm in modern neurology, psychology,
and philosophy concerning the relationship between the mind and brain. If I didn’t know better I might think
Graziano, based on the seriousness with which he writes, has succumbed to a
neo-Cartesian dualism where the mind/self/soul can actually live on after the
death of the body. He is relatively
unconcerned about these problems compared to his interest in what psychological
and cultural impact such a technology might have on Humankind. For me, his ignoring of these problems makes
speculation about the psychological and cultural ramifications of a
virtual-reality afterlife, well, speculation for naught. Graziano, in fact, dismisses the problem of
how a simulated self can be the same as a real self as follows:
I have heard
people say that the technology will never catch on. People won’t be tempted because a duplicate
of you, no matter how realistic, is still not you. But I doubt that such existential concerns
will have much of an impact once the technology arrives. You already wake up every day as a marvelous
copy of a previous you, and nobody has paralyzing metaphysical concerns about
that. If you die and are replaced by a
really good computer simulation, it’ll just seem to you like you entered a
scanner and came out somewhere else.”
Really? Graziano actually
believes that one day the technology will come that will make a duplicate you,
a real you. He has no qualms about asserting the high
probability that someday we will be able to scan and capture the brain wiring
of our memories, emotions, and ways of thinking and making decisions and upload
them into computer hardware. This, he
claims, will be a “second version of you” that could “live in a simulated world
and hardly know the difference.”
(italics mine) He pauses and asks
himself if such an incredible thing could ever be possible, “whether we could
upload someone’s mind to a computer,” and concludes “yes, almost
certainly.” … “In fact,” Graziano says, “the more I think
about this possible future, the more it seems inevitable.” It is numbing to think that one day a scanned
replica of a person’s self would be indistinguishable from his/her biologically-embedded self. This, I
believe, is highly unlikely because a self, the full range of the psychological
and social aspects of a living self, are not, as I argue below, properties that
can be captured on scans or electrode printouts. It is not very likely that full living selves
could continue to exist as the same full living selves if they are separated
from their biological body-brains.
How, according to Graziano, will the replication of a
self-endowed mind be accomplished? He
thinks that “the pattern of connectivity among neurons contains the essence of
the machine. If you could measure how
each neurone connects to its neighbours, you’d have all the data you need to recreate
that mind. Scientists," he says, "will
likely one day be able create an artificial mind by copying the wiring already
present in a real brain. … [T]he essence of a human mind is contained in
its pattern of connectivity. Your
connectome [a map or wiring diagram of every neuronal connection in a brain],
simulated in a computer, would recreate your conscious mind. … It
seems a no-brainer (excuse the pun) that we will be able to scan, map, and
store the data on every neuronal connection with a person’s head. It is only a matter of time, and a timescale
of five to 10 decades seems about right.”
Graziano’s treatment of the psychological, social, and
cultural impact of a future virtual-reality afterlife focuses on the meaning of being an individual and being alive. “For starters,” he says, “it seems inevitable
that we will tend to treat human life and death much more casually. People will be more willing to put themselves
and others in danger.” He also
speculates on the sanctity of digital life, human rights, experimentation on
simulated consciousnesses, and the criminality of pulling the plug on someone’s
“simulated person.” These issues, he
says, are “the tip of a nasty philosophical [and legal] iceberg we seem to be
sailing towards.”
Toward the end of his article, I Graziano raised had my
estimation of his concern for humanity.
He gives what I at first took as a nod to the impact a virtual-reality
afterlife will have on the self, the person, our individuality: “If simulated minds can be run in a simulated
world, then the most transformative change, the deepest shift in human
experience would be the loss of individuality – the integration of knowledge
into a single intelligence, smarter and more capable than anything that could
exist in the natural world.” But
Graziano chooses not to discuss the possibility this might result in a tragic
reduction or loss of our humanness, humanity, or humaneness, much less the
destructive effect it likely would have on civilization. Instead he bounds forward to foretell the
possibility of merging virtual minds and asks “what is to stop people from
merging into überpeople who are combinations of wisdom, experience, and memory
beyond anything possible in biology? Two
minds, three minds, 10, pretty soon everyone is linked mind-to-mind. The concept of separate identity is
lost. The need for simulated bodies
walking in a simulated world is lost.
The need for simulated food and simulated landscapes and simulated
voices disappears. Instead a single
platform of thought, knowledge, and constant realization emerges. ...
Real life, our life, shrinks in importance until it becomes a kind of
larval phase.”
In the end, Graziano, in a clear expression of humanism, regards the scenarios he describes to be somewhat
“intriguing,” but for the most part, “horrifying.” Although he finds comfort in the fact that he
will not live to see such a transformation in human life, as I do, he is
optimistic that we will somehow muddle through, as we have since we first took
up living in the forest margins and grasslands of East Africa, millions of years ago: “We always manage to live more-or-less
comfortably,” he says, “in a world that would have frightened and offended the
previous generations.”
Conclusion
A self begins in a newborn baby who two members of the
community intentionally or unintentionally produce through sexual intercourse. In this new body the emergence of a self
comes into its initial non-material existence as an accompaniment to the proactive
sentience of the young brain-mind. It
emerges from a biological substrate that is responding to the food, shelter, comfort,
and language provided by the parent(s).
From this biological foundation, with its attendant genomic propensities
and the social and cultural milieu an individual is born into, a self is slowly and gradually, over a number of years, created.
Throughout the ensuing life of the individual the self is
maintained and modified as the individual’s efforts and conditions will allow, and
in response to his/her experience of the natural and social worlds. Through the process of enculturation the
self-bearing individual becomes socially indebted to the family and community
of his birth, and bound to the moral systems, prescriptions, proscriptions,
sanctions, and actions of the various groups he lives within throughout his/her
life. The brain produces the self which
is an emergent property of consciousness.
When the body and its brain die, the self ceases to actively exist.
The rights and ownership of the living self/person are
sociocultural constructs and therefore are not inherent in the body or
“aliveness” of any human. However, Locke,
Rothbard, and Macpherson’s respective claims (see Médaille) that every human owns
his person/self are true. But their
claims are only true to the degree that an individual is able and willing to
assert such a claim of ownership, and whether or not his communities of
livelihood and residence at any given time affirm that assertion.
More important than the question of do I own my self is the
declaration: I am my self. A self does not come into existence in
response to a call from the community. It
cannot belong exclusively to or be owned exclusively by a body or a community. It originates, exists, and dies as an active
emergent entity of the body. The self
lives, yes lives, each day by
directing the body to behave within the natural and social worlds based on the
self’s understandings, needs, and desires.
The brain produces the self in a manner that is not yet known, but the
brain is not the self. If you probe the
brain with scans or electrodes you will not find the self because it is an immaterial, though animate, manifestation of the activities of the brain.
But, you say, if the self is produced by the brain, then the self must be found in the brain. Imagine trying to understand the composition and activity of light by tracing a flashlight beam to the reflective cone around the bulb. Then examine the bulb, then the filament within it, then the streams of electrons traveling through the filament. This has led you to the batteries and their electro-chemical composition and processes. Despite your best analysis and description of the chain of events that produce the light, the internal aspects of the batteries will not tell you what the light itself is composed of, or what role the light of the flashlight plays in the natural and social worlds. The same is true of the mind/self/person. Someday, how the brain produces the mind/self/person will likely become known. But this will tell us little about what the mind/self/person is and what it does for individuals and communities in the worlds in which it lives.
But, you say, if the self is produced by the brain, then the self must be found in the brain. Imagine trying to understand the composition and activity of light by tracing a flashlight beam to the reflective cone around the bulb. Then examine the bulb, then the filament within it, then the streams of electrons traveling through the filament. This has led you to the batteries and their electro-chemical composition and processes. Despite your best analysis and description of the chain of events that produce the light, the internal aspects of the batteries will not tell you what the light itself is composed of, or what role the light of the flashlight plays in the natural and social worlds. The same is true of the mind/self/person. Someday, how the brain produces the mind/self/person will likely become known. But this will tell us little about what the mind/self/person is and what it does for individuals and communities in the worlds in which it lives.
The manifestation of the self arises from and is dependent
on the brain but it is not the brain. It
functions according to principles and processes different from the principles
and processes of the brain. The self is
an amalgam of the physio-chemical processes of the brain and an individual’s mental and emotional states and the learned
concepts it (s/he) has assimilated. It
is both of the brain yet separate from it.
Understanding the brain part of the self is neither a complete
understanding of the self, nor a complete understanding of its essence or a ultimate
rendering of it.
Upon the death of the body, the self has a passive
immortality only (as far as we know) in any surviving artifact it compels its body to produce or modify, in the memories of others, or as described in any
written, printed, recorded, or radio-transmitted media in which it might
appear. Minus its record in artifacts,
memories, or media, there is no postmortem, eternal evidence that a particular
self ever existed. It cannot be found in
the living body that produces, houses, and empowers it, and it certainly is not
to be found in the corpse it once inhabited.
The self exists in the inner world of each individual as a useful means of unifying, animating, and making personally and socially coherent the processes of the brain and the rest of the body. The self is a representative produced by the brain that serves as an interfacee between the brain and the natural and social worlds. Brains themselves cannot do any of the following: talk, find mates, reproduce, form resource-procuring communities, build structures, produce art, write love letters, vote, sign peace treaties, or otherwise socially bond with other brains. Selves and persons can do all these. Without the self, humans would be unguided, insentient, protoplasmic objects. With it, we become greatly empowered subjects and citizens.
The self exists in the inner world of each individual as a useful means of unifying, animating, and making personally and socially coherent the processes of the brain and the rest of the body. The self is a representative produced by the brain that serves as an interfacee between the brain and the natural and social worlds. Brains themselves cannot do any of the following: talk, find mates, reproduce, form resource-procuring communities, build structures, produce art, write love letters, vote, sign peace treaties, or otherwise socially bond with other brains. Selves and persons can do all these. Without the self, humans would be unguided, insentient, protoplasmic objects. With it, we become greatly empowered subjects and citizens.
Further Reading
on the Self
Self, Self, Self by Rick Lewis, Philosophy Now, Issue 97, July/August 2013
How Old Is The Self? by Frank S. Robinson, Philosophy Now, Issue 97, July/August
2013
A Philosophical Identity Crisis by Chris Durante, Philosophy Now, Issue 97, July/August
2013
The Illusion of Self by Sam Woolfe, Philosophy Now, Issue 97, July/August 2013
Focusing on the Brain, Ignoring the Body by Alessandro
Colarossi, Philosophy Now, Issue 97,
July/August 2013
Is The Buddhist ‘No-Self’ Doctrine Compatible With PursuingNirvana? by Katie Javanaud, Philosophy
Now, Issue 97, July/August 2013